Monday, September 30, 2019
Justice in Antigone
Antiquity and the 19th Century (Ulfers) William Rauscher Thursday, 9:30AM Justice in Antigone In Sophoclesââ¬â¢ Antigone, two notions of ââ¬Ëjusticeââ¬â¢ are presented, which conflict with each other. Creonââ¬â¢s form of justice rewards the loyal Eteocles and punishes the traitor Polyneices, by refusing to give Polyneices proper burial rites. This form of justice directly conflicts with Antigoneââ¬â¢s idea of justice, which doesnââ¬â¢t differentiate between the ââ¬Å"wickedâ⬠and the ââ¬Å"just. â⬠These two conflicting thoughts on justice illustrate two classic philosophies.Creon represents a Paramenidean view of justice, while Antigone represents a Heraclitean view of justice. Paramenidean thought splits the world into two systems, where ââ¬Å"Beingâ⬠is primary and ââ¬Å"Becomingâ⬠is secondary (Ulfers, Lecture). To Paramenides, ââ¬Å"Beingâ⬠is associated with the idea of ââ¬Å"onenessâ⬠and ââ¬Å"timelessness,â⬠while a ny ââ¬Å"Becomingâ⬠or process is an illusion produced by the senses. This dualistic worldview simplifies everyday occurrences and thoughts into opposites, which are unchangeable. In contrast, Heraclitean thought presents ââ¬Å"Becomingâ⬠as primary, while ââ¬Å"Beingâ⬠is secondary (Ulfers, Lecture).Heraclitus regards change and temporality as ultimate in a perpetual process of ââ¬Å"Becoming. â⬠Heraclitus goes on to argue that opposites are simultaneously present in a state known as chiasmic unity. Chiasmic unity constitutes a paradoxical unity of opposites, which binds opposites together and keeps them apart. Heraclitean thought favors the logic of ââ¬Å"both/and,â⬠which violates the Paramenidean logic of ââ¬Å"either/or. â⬠Antigone presents a Heraclitean view of justice in a conversation with her sister Ismene abut Creonââ¬â¢s proclamation that their brother, Polyneices, will ot receive proper burial rites. Antigone determines that Creon has no authority to dictate burial rites: ââ¬Å"It is not for him [Creon] to keep me from my ownâ⬠(Sophocles, 163). By choosing to defy Creonââ¬â¢s decree, Antigone accepts her fate as ââ¬Å"a criminal-but a religious one,â⬠revealing that she wants to make her act of defiance a public example. Antigone does not fear Creonââ¬â¢s threat of punishment because she follows a different form of justice based on a higher religious authority.Religion functions in a chiasmic structure, where the opposite values of ââ¬Å"wickedâ⬠and ââ¬Å"just,â⬠lose their oppositional aspects (Ulfers, Lecture). Antigoneââ¬â¢s commitment to a Heraclitean view of justice allows her to defy the sovereign, yet keep her honor: ââ¬Å"No suffering of mine will be enough to make me die ignoblyâ⬠(Sophocles 165). In contrast, Ismene chooses to follow Creonââ¬â¢s interpretation of justice because he is the current ruling power, whose authority is unquestioned. She is not a ble to see past the ââ¬Å"either/orâ⬠logic Creon has imposed on his people.As a wiser, older sister, Ismene warns Antigone about disobeying Creon, pleading with Antigone to come to her senses: ââ¬Å"â⬠¦and see how miserable our end shall be if in the teeth of law we shall transgress against the sovereignââ¬â¢s decree and powerâ⬠¦Extravagant action is not sensibleâ⬠(Sophocles, 163). Ismene determines that Antigoneââ¬â¢s intended action is flawed because it goes beyond the simplicity of following the sovereignââ¬â¢s law. Despite these warnings, Antigone is compelled to defy Creonââ¬â¢s proclamation as a result of her Heraclitean view of justice.Creon confronts Antigone for defying his decree. In contrast to Antigone, Creon represents the Paramenidean view of justice, which is based on an oppositional order of wicked and just, punishment and reward (Ulfers, Lecture). Creon extends these distinctions to the realm of the dead: ââ¬Å"My enemy is still my enemy even in deathâ⬠(Sophocles 181). Creon believes that by extending the intolerance of treachery into deathââ¬â¢s realm, he will set an example that will dissuade any future uprisings against his rule.Antigone shows no remorse for her actions, believing that Creonââ¬â¢s rule does not extend to the realm of the dead: ââ¬Å"â⬠¦it was not Zeus that made the proclamation; nor did Justice, which lives with those below, enact such laws as that, for mankind. I did not believe your proclamation had such power to enable one who will someday die to override Godââ¬â¢s ordinancesâ⬠(Sophocles 178). Antigone disagrees with Creon, since death is inevitable and is neither considered a punishment nor a reward. In this sense, judgment is suspended in the realm of death.She feels that the mortal Creon cannot make a proclamation that governs the realm of the dead. Antigone embodies a ââ¬Å"lawâ⬠that revolves around the chiasmic unity of the opposite values of honor and dishonor attributed to Etocles and Polyneices, respectively (Ulfers, Lecture). She will not give allegiance to the temporal rules of Creon, since she will be in conflict with the higher authority of the gods regarding the realm of death: ââ¬Å"The god of death demands these rites for bothâ⬠(Sophocles 181).As a result of Antigoneââ¬â¢s public display of disobedience toward Creonââ¬â¢s rule, Creon believes that he is forced to fulfill the justified punishment of death on Antigone. In order to uphold his authority as a good ruler, he feels that he has to rule with intolerance toward disobedience: ââ¬Å"The man the city set up in authority must be obeyed in small things and in just but also in their oppositesâ⬠(Sophocles, 187). In Creonââ¬â¢s mind, creating a victorious rule means inflexible justice, order, and discipline.This unchanging mentality of a strict separation of being either loyal or disloyal and receiving either reward or punishment represents a Pa ramenidean view of justice. His form of justice is devoid of leniency and mercy, only seeing his own perspective on justice. Creon finally realizes the true ââ¬Å"injusticeâ⬠of his law only after the tragic deaths of his son, wife, and Antigone: ââ¬Å"The mistakes of a blinded man are themselves rigid and laden with deathâ⬠(Sophocles, 209).His inflexible decrees blinded him from true justice by locking him into a rigid Paramenidean view of the world. After facing unparalleled tragedies, he ultimately has gained insight into Antigoneââ¬â¢s ââ¬Å"justice. â⬠Creon has switched from the Paramenidean separation of opposites to the chiasmic unity of opposites: ââ¬Å"Everything in my hands is crossedâ⬠(Sophocles, 212). Creon is now able to comprehend that not everything can be categorized into separate distinctions to be judged, seeming to accept the Heraclitean view of justice.Creon sees the error in his notion of justice, but he is too late to prevent the t ragedy that befalls him. His absolute power of ruling combined with his pride and arrogance leads him to be blinded to Antigoneââ¬â¢s beliefs. At the end of the play, Creon gains ââ¬Å"wisdomâ⬠from his ââ¬Å"unwelcome fateâ⬠realizing that he ââ¬Å"[should] have kept the old accepted lawsâ⬠(Sophocles 204, 212). This realization bestows upon him the knowledge to rule in favor of the ââ¬Å"both/andâ⬠Heraclitean view of justice, rather than the ââ¬Å"either/orâ⬠Paramenidean view of justice that he once followed.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.